Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646-1716)
(Redirected from Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz)
Jump to navigation
Jump to search
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646-1716) was a person.
- Context:
- He invented Leibniz's Notation.
- …
- Counter-Example(s):
- See: Mathematician, Philosopher, Calculus, Law of Continuity, Transcendental Law of Homogeneity.
References
2014
- (Wikipedia, 2014) ⇒ http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Gottfried_Wilhelm_Leibniz Retrieved:2014-7-17.
- Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz ([1] or ; July 1, 1646 – November 14, 1716) was a German mathematician and philosopher. He occupies a prominent place in the history of mathematics and the history of philosophy. Leibniz developed calculus independently of Isaac Newton, and Leibniz's mathematical notation has been widely used ever since it was published. It was only in the 20th century that his Law of Continuity and Transcendental Law of Homogeneity found mathematical implementation (by means of non-standard analysis). He became one of the most prolific inventors in the field of mechanical calculators. While working on adding automatic multiplication and division to Pascal's calculator, he was the first to describe a pinwheel calculator in 1685 [2] and invented the Leibniz wheel, used in the arithmometer, the first mass-produced mechanical calculator. He also refined the binary number system, which is the foundation of virtually all digital computers. In philosophy, Leibniz is most noted for his optimism, e.g., his conclusion that our Universe is, in a restricted sense, the best possible one that God could have created. Leibniz, along with René Descartes and Baruch Spinoza, was one of the three great 17th century advocates of rationalism. The work of Leibniz anticipated modern logic and analytic philosophy, but his philosophy also looks back to the scholastic tradition, in which conclusions are produced by applying reason to first principles or prior definitions rather than to empirical evidence. Leibniz made major contributions to physics and technology, and anticipated notions that surfaced much later in philosophy, probability theory, biology, medicine, geology, psychology, linguistics, and computer science. He wrote works on philosophy, politics, law, ethics, theology, history, and philology. Leibniz's contributions to this vast array of subjects were scattered in various learned journals, in tens of thousands of letters, and in unpublished manuscripts. He wrote in several languages, but primarily in Latin, French, and German. [3] There is no complete gathering of the writings of Leibniz.
- ↑ "Leibniz" entry in Collins English Dictionary, HarperCollins Publishers, 1998.
- ↑ David Smith, p.173-181 (1929)
- ↑ Roughly 40%, 30%, and 15%, respectively.www.gwlb.de. Leibniz-Nachlass (i.e. Legacy of Leibniz), Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Bibliothek (one of the three Official Libraries of the German state Lower Saxony).
1684
- (Leibniz, 1684) ⇒ Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. (1684). “Nova methodus pro maximis et minimis (New method for maximums and minimums); translated in Struik, D. J., 1969. A Source Book in Mathematics, 1200–1800. Harvard University Press: 271–81.
1673
- (Leibniz, 1684) ⇒ Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. (1684). “Confessio philosophi (A Philosopher's Creed); an English translation is available.
1671
- (Leibniz, 1684) ⇒ Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. (1684). “Hypothesis Physica Nova (New Physical Hypothesis); Loemker §8.I (partial).
1666
- (Leibniz, 1684) ⇒ Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. (1684). “De Arte Combinatoria (On the Art of Combination); partially translated in Loemker §1 and Parkinson (1966).