Consistency

From GM-RKB
Jump to navigation Jump to search

A Consistency is a statement that does contain a contradiction.



References

2017

  • (Wikipedia, 2017) ⇒ https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Consistency Retrieved:2017-6-4.
    • In classical deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not contain a contradiction. [1] [2] The lack of contradiction can be defined in either semantic or syntactic terms. The semantic definition states that a theory is consistent if and only if it has a model, i.e., there exists an interpretation under which all formulas in the theory are true. This is the sense used in traditional Aristotelian logic, although in contemporary mathematical logic the term satisfiable is used instead. The syntactic definition states a theory [math]\displaystyle{ T }[/math] is consistent if and only if there is no formula [math]\displaystyle{ \phi }[/math] such that both [math]\displaystyle{ \phi }[/math] and its negation [math]\displaystyle{ \lnot\phi }[/math] are elements of the set [math]\displaystyle{ T }[/math] . Let [math]\displaystyle{ A }[/math] be set of closed sentences (informally "axioms") and [math]\displaystyle{ \langle A\rangle }[/math] the set of closed sentences provable from [math]\displaystyle{ A }[/math] under some (specified, possibly implicitly) formal deductive system. The set of axioms [math]\displaystyle{ A }[/math] is consistent when [math]\displaystyle{ \langle A \rangle }[/math] is. [3]

      If there exists a deductive system for which these semantic and syntactic definitions are equivalent for any theory formulated in a particular deductive logic, the logic is called complete. The completeness of the sentential calculus was proved by Paul Bernays in 1918[4] and Emil Post in 1921, [5] while the completeness of predicate calculus was proved by Kurt Gödel in 1930, [6] and consistency proofs for arithmetics restricted with respect to the induction axiom schema were proved by Ackermann (1924), von Neumann (1927) and Herbrand (1931). [7] Stronger logics, such as second-order logic, are not complete. A consistency proof is a mathematical proof that a particular theory is consistent. [8] The early development of mathematical proof theory was driven by the desire to provide finitary consistency proofs for all of mathematics as part of Hilbert's program. Hilbert's program was strongly impacted by incompleteness theorems, which showed that sufficiently strong proof theories cannot prove their own consistency (provided that they are in fact consistent).

      Although consistency can be proved by means of model theory, it is often done in a purely syntactical way, without any need to reference some model of the logic. The cut-elimination (or equivalently the normalization of the underlying calculus if there is one) implies the consistency of the calculus: since there is obviously no cut-free proof of falsity, there is no contradiction in general.

  1. Tarski 1946 states it this way: "A deductive theory is called CONSISTENT or NON-CONTRADICTORY if no two asserted statements of this theory contradict each other, or in other words, if of any two contradictory sentences . . . at least one cannot be proved," (p. 135) where Tarski defines contradictory as follows: "With the help of the word not one forms the NEGATION of any sentence; two sentences, of which the first is a negation of the second, are called CONTRADICTORY SENTENCES" (p. 20). This definition requires a notion of "proof". Gödel in his 1931 defines the notion this way: "The class of provable formulas is defined to be the smallest class of formulas that contains the axioms and is closed under the relation "immediate consequence", i.e., formula c of a and b is defined as an immediate consequence in terms of modus ponens or substitution; cf Gödel 1931 van Heijenoort 1967:601. Tarski defines "proof" informally as "statements follow one another in a definite order according to certain principles . . . and accompanied by considerations intended to establish their validity[true conclusion for all true premises -- Reichenbach 1947:68]" cf Tarski 1946:3. Kleene 1952 defines the notion with respect to either an induction or as to paraphrase) a finite sequence of formulas such that each formula in the sequence is either an axiom or an "immediate consequence" of the preceding formulas; "A proof is said to be a proof of its last formula, and this formula is said to be (formally) provable or be a (formal) theorem" cf Kleene 1952:83.
  2. see Paraconsistent logic
  3. Let [math]\displaystyle{ L }[/math] be a signature, [math]\displaystyle{ T }[/math] a theory in [math]\displaystyle{ L_{\infty \omega} }[/math] and [math]\displaystyle{ \phi }[/math] a sentence in [math]\displaystyle{ L_{\infty\omega} }[/math] . We say that [math]\displaystyle{ \phi }[/math] is a consequence of [math]\displaystyle{ T }[/math] , or that [math]\displaystyle{ T }[/math] entails [math]\displaystyle{ \phi }[/math] , in symbols [math]\displaystyle{ T \vdash \phi }[/math] , if every model of [math]\displaystyle{ T }[/math] is a model of [math]\displaystyle{ \phi }[/math] . (In particular if [math]\displaystyle{ T }[/math] has no models then [math]\displaystyle{ T }[/math] entails [math]\displaystyle{ \phi }[/math] .) Warning: we don't require that if [math]\displaystyle{ T \vdash \phi }[/math] then there is a proof of [math]\displaystyle{ \phi }[/math] from [math]\displaystyle{ T }[/math] . In any case, with infinitary languages it's not always clear what would constitute a proof. Some writers use [math]\displaystyle{ T\vdash\phi }[/math] to mean that [math]\displaystyle{ \phi }[/math] is deducible from [math]\displaystyle{ T }[/math] in some particular formal proof calculus, and they write [math]\displaystyle{ T \models \phi }[/math] for our notion of entailment (a notation which clashes with our [math]\displaystyle{ A \models \phi }[/math]). For first-order logic the two kinds of entailment coincide by the completeness theorem for the proof calculus in question. We say that [math]\displaystyle{ \phi }[/math] is valid, or is a logical theorem, in symbols [math]\displaystyle{ \vdash \phi }[/math] , if [math]\displaystyle{ \phi }[/math] is true in every [math]\displaystyle{ L }[/math] -structure. We say that [math]\displaystyle{ \phi }[/math] is consistent if [math]\displaystyle{ \phi }[/math] is true in some [math]\displaystyle{ L }[/math] -structure. Likewise we say that a theory [math]\displaystyle{ T }[/math] is consistent if it has a model. We say that two theories S and T in L infinity omega are equivalent if they have the same models, i.e. if Mod(S) = Mod(T). (Please note definition of Mod(T) on p. 30 ...)

    A Shorter Model Theory by Wilfrid Hodges, p. 37

  4. van Heijenoort 1967:265 states that Bernays determined the independence of the axioms of Principia Mathematica, a result not published until 1926, but he says nothing about Bernays proving their consistency.
  5. Post proves both consistency and completeness of the propositional calculus of PM, cf van Heijenoort's commentary and Post's 1931 Introduction to a general theory of elementary propositions in van Heijenoort 1967:264ff. Also Tarski 1946:134ff.
  6. cf van Heijenoort's commentary and Gödel's 1930 The completeness of the axioms of the functional calculus of logic in van Heijenoort 1967:582ff
  7. cf van Heijenoort's commentary and Herbrand's 1930 On the consistency of arithmetic in van Heijenoort 1967:618ff.
  8. Informally, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory is ordinarily assumed; some dialects of informal mathematics customarily assume the axiom of choice in addition.